In 1970, Geoffrey Hartman, a young professor of literature, brought his friend Paul de Man to join him in the English department at Yale. In the ensuing years, the two of them became close colleagues in the American reception of Jacques Derrida for whom, in 1975, they arranged a recurring visiting appointment. The three became close friends and together changed the way American professors and students thought about literature. But they couldn’t have come from more different backgrounds. At the age of nine, Hartman had been in Kindertransport, the program that evacuated Jewish children from Germany to England in 1939. He didn’t see his mother again for 6 years. Derrida had to leave his school in Algiers when the quota for Jewish students was reduced and Algerian Jews lost their citizenship. De Man, it turns out, was a crassly opportunistic Nazi collaborator who wrote a series of anti-Semitic articles in the Belgian press in the ‘40s. What does it mean that these three, with such different histories, could agree on so much about literature and philosophy?
Reading the reviews of Evelyn Barish’s new book on de Man,
I couldn’t help but think of John Howard Yoder. As de
Man’s students and colleagues have struggled to come to
grips with his Nazi past, so Mennonite theologians and others
are now, finally, trying to learn how to think about
Yoder’s violence against women. We all owe Barb Graber
and Ruth Krall a great deal for refusing to let us (by which I
mean myself and other Mennonite theologians who write about and
teach Yoder) continue to ignore the facts of Yoder’s
violence. Graber asked us to do something specific: Welcome,
encourage and make efforts to include analysis of the
astoundingly ironic disconnect between Yoder’s orthodoxy
and his severe lack of orthopraxy.
In what follows, thanks to Mennonite Life, I take up
that invitation. I begin with de Man’s case not to imply
that such a task is impossible, but to acknowledge how complex
it can be. All ideas are products of a social location. But, as
the de Man story shows, how they are so, is an
incredibly complex question. There is no straight line of
determination between life and work; there are countless
crooked and tangled threads. In what follows I try to identify
and follow one thread in Yoder.
While I am a theologian, deeply indebted to the work of Yoder, my teaching responsibilities tend to be for EMU’s Religious Studies curriculum. So aside from an essay in our introductory Christian ethics course and an essay in an anthropology of religion course, I have only taught Yoder at length in one class, a topics seminar on political theology in the Fall of 2011. That seminar spent one class period (out of four on Yoder) talking about Yoder’s sexual violence and if and how we should relate that to his work.
This was new territory for me. For most of my academic life I
read Yoder and once co-edited a book about him assuming that
the life and the work could be kept separate. I wasn’t
exactly comfortable with this state of affairs, but I was at a
loss to know what to do about it. I wasn’t ready to deny
that there were connections between Yoder’s life and his
work, but I also couldn’t see those connections and
lacked the imagination or energy to discover them. Anyhow,
didn’t a wide range of twentieth century literary
criticism from the New Critics to the Yale poststructuralists
teach that authors didn’t matter and hence texts could be
liberated from the interpretive tyranny of things like
authorial intention and biography? Though it makes me cringe to
recall, in response to concerns raised about Yoder at an MCC
peace committee meeting in the late ‘90s I blithely
quoted Alexandre Nehamas’s famous lines about Nietzsche,
In engaging with his works, we are not engaging with the
miserable little man who wrote them, but with the philosopher
who emerges through them.
But by the Fall of 2011, I had begun to think about it a bit
differently, in part because of the publication of Alex
Sider’s Friendship, Alienation, Love: Stanley
Hauerwas and John Howard Yoder.
Sider’s essay doesn’t mention Yoder’s
violence against women, but upon reading it I was convinced
that the most plausible connections between Yoder’s life
and work would be drawn through the argument Sider makes so I
assigned it to my students that day.
The problem Sider’s essay identifies and explores is the
tendency in Yoder to resolve issues of personal and
existential alienation by treating the unhappiness many people
experience as a kind of misdiagnosis that can be solved via a
judicious application of ecclesiology
(418), thereby
compounding the alienation. A striking example is the Festival
Quarterly interview with Yoder where he was asked if he was
happy, to which he responded, I haven’t found it
very useful to ask that question.
According to Sider, a
similar attitude pervades Yoder’s work. We consistently
see an avoidance any talk of selfhood, psychology, or
subjectivity in favor of more talk about ecclesiology and
church practices. Here is an example of a Yoder passage that
Sider rightly finds both problematic and typical. The concerns
of those evangelists who understand salvation as restored
selfhood, liberation from anxiety and guilt are not
wrong…BUT ALL OF THIS IS NOT THE GOSPEL. This is just
the bonus, the wrapping paper thrown in when you buy the meat,
the ‘everything’ which will be added, without your
taking thought for it, if we seek first the kingdom of God and
his righteousness!
(433) Leaving aside the bizarre metaphor of
bloody packing paper as bonus,
the claim is that if you
try really hard to be a radical messianic alternative
community, then your shattered selfhood, your anxiety and guilt
will take care of themselves. This isn’t necessarily or
always wrong. It is sometimes true that the immersion in good
work can be therapeutic, but in that case it isn’t a bonus
;
it is the thing itself or at least a bonus deserving a far more
dignified metaphor than wrapping paper destined for the trash
bin. And it often is wrong, just insofar as church practices
can often only be therapeutic if we deliberately and explicitly
talk about, not ignore, affective registers of desire
and delight
(434).
Why does Yoder end up here? Why does it seem like ecclesiology
and psychology have to exist in a zero-sum relationship where
the ecclesiology has to drive out the psychological? One answer
may be that Yoder, like many other pacifist theologians, fears
that moral psychology, the attempt to understand why the good
is difficult, can become an excuse for why the good is
unachievable. Another answer is that Yoder inherits from Barth
a suspicion of pietism’s emphasis on the individual
believer’s subjectivity, of the way pietism could seem to
shrink the stage of Gods’ work from the cosmos to the
individual heart.
Sider’s essay helps us see that both answers function in
Yoder as a flight from himself, a flight he desperately needed
for all the wrong reasons. Refusing to think theologically
about any selves makes it a lot easier to avoid thinking about
his own self. His response to Festival Quarterly’s
question about happiness should have been I have found
it very useful to avoid that question.
Or I have found
the question too hard to bear.
Of course, Yoder wasn’t just in flight from himself. He
was in flight from his victims. But it is a poor account of
selfhood that makes those two flights alternatives. It would be
a mistake to replace Yoder’s other without self with the
old Cartesian/pietist self without other. Self and other are
always necessarily intertwined. At its most basic level, it is
simply that who I am is always someone in a range of
relationships. So I may be a spouse, a brother or sister, a
parent and/or child, a teacher and/or student, an employer
and/or employee, a victim and victimizer. In each of these
cases, to know who I am, to say, I am a brother,
is to
make a statement about another. And to deny or ignore that I am
a brother is to deny or ignore the brother or sister.
It so happens that the previous year had been my first
opportunity to teach my way through Augustine’s Confessions.
The conventional Anabaptist view has long been that Yoder and
Augustine are opposites. I am sympathetic with, and have
learned a lot from, the efforts of theologians like Gerald
Schlabach
and Charlie Collier
who have tried to upset that consensus by reading Yoder and
Augustine alongside each other. But in at least one respect,
perhaps we should resume thinking of them in opposition, though
now for very different reasons. Augustine, whose penitent
self-awareness, produced by a range of friendships, made for
the most profound moral psychology we have and Yoder, whose
flight from himself and violence against others, made for a
striking absence of even the most rudimentary moral psychology.
Augustine loved the moment in the parable of the prodigal son
upon which the story hinges. Luke 15.17 begins he
returned to himself.
But nothing is more important than noting
that returning to himself, quite clearly means returning both
in his immediate thoughts and in his subsequent action to the
one he had sinned against.
Is any of this plausible as an attempt to account for the astoundingly
ironic disconnect
between Yoder’s life and work? I think
it is, but I began with the de Man case in order to flag my
awareness of how difficult such an undertaking is. For some,
the complexity has been a reason to say that they can’t
see any connection at all between Yoder’s life and work.
That claim isn’t necessarily wrong; connections are hard
to see. And it is usually good scholarly practice to be
confident in your thesis before articulating an argument. But
in some cases, such as this one, the best scholarly practice
may be something like the opposite. It is to cut loose our
imaginations to toss up risky experimental, hypothetical theses
not because we are sure they are right but precisely because we
are not sure of anything except that such a practice may be the
only way a genuinely illuminating conversation of the kind
Graber and Krall are demanding can become fruitful.